Two-faced: Tom Nairn’s Faces of Nationalism Revisited

Faces of Nationalism: Janus Revisited, Tom Nairn, Verso Books

Reviewed by David McCrone

In an essay on Thomas Carlyle in London Review of Books (14th Dec 2023), the writer Stefan Collini commented on Tom Nairn’s ‘caustic Scottish sarcasm’. Certainly, Tom took no prisoners in his writing, while in person he was a gentle soul, always good company. Tom and I introduced a Masters degree in Nationalism Studies at Edinburgh University in 1994. Students could hardly believe that this was same Tom Nairn who excoriated in print. We had the advantage of having the Tory MP for Ayr, Phil Gallie, asking a question in the House of Commons as to why the university was indoctrinating students into nationalism, thus proving once more that there is no such thing as bad publicity. 

Tom’s writing needs no introduction here. He is best known for The Break-Up of Britain (1977, 1981, 2003, and 2021), The Enchanted Glass: Britain and its Monarchy (1994, 2011), After Britain: New Labour and the Return of Scotland (2001), and the book discussed here, Faces of Nationalism: Janus Revisited (1997, and 2005). I recall the review of The Enchanted Glass, by the political writer RW Johnson who observed: ‘Nairn writes with a bitterness that is truly wonderful and has a line in highly literate, off-hand abuse which is extremely funny’. Pace Johnson, it’s not bitterness which was Tom’s forte, but scorn. 

Faces is probably Tom’s most ‘academic’ book, although it consists of essays published, above all, in London Review of Books during the early 1990s, as well as lectures he gave in Edinburgh and elsewhere. Tom observed of Ernest Gellner with whom he taught at the European University in Prague after 1989 that ‘the true subject of all modern philosophy is industrialisation’ was the kind of remark which Gellner loved most, ‘an acrid mixture of surprise, denigration and humour’: that sounds like Tom too. And yet he thought that Gellner missed the point in his ‘astringent aperçu’, because it didn’t go far enough. The true subject of modern philosophy was not industrialisation but ‘its immensely complex and variegated aftershock – nationalism’ (p.1). 

Tom’s (and Ernest’s) key point was that the ‘common man’ (and woman) was a nationalist because ‘industrialisation required a general culture and language to make it work, and the effective culture was usually the popular-national one’. Far from nationalism being some exotic cultural outgrowth, it became the default position. It was, however, taken-for-granted and implicit in large part because it could not speak its name following its close association with Nazism and Fascism. It was fine to talk about ‘the national interest’, and to assume the naturalness of states – usually as ‘nation-states’, as if the cultural (nation) and the political (state) were in simple correspondence. There developed what Gellner called the dark gods theory of nationalism, that it needed to be kept locked up, in a Pandora’s box, lest the virus escape and infect the body politic. Since 1945, that metaphor proved longstanding, and following George Orwell’s essay, it was okay to be ‘patriotic’ but not ‘nationalistic’. The problem however was, and is, that the distinction is inoperable, except as claim and accusation. It doesn’t hold analytical water.

The problem too is that nationalism is protean; it takes many shapes and forms, and in Tom’s word ‘faces’. It is a chameleon. The rise and rise of right-wing populism across the world elicits the response: ‘See? I told you so.’ Dark gods again. The Scottish variety drew various responses: that it was hiding its true values based on social and cultural divisions, or that it wasn’t really ‘nationalism’ at all, but simply a way of doing territorial politics. Tom had no truck with any of this. He bought into Gellner’s account of nationalism that it was ‘the true subject of modern philosophy of industrialisation; the nation, not the steam engine and the computer’ (p.17). Tom was not entirely convinced by Gellner’s functionalist account of nationalism as a necessary form of civic politics, required by modernity. That was too neat. Nairn thought that the way to understand nationalism lay in a complex assortment of genetics, archaeology, linguistics, psychology, anthropology, religion and peasant studies. Thus, ‘far from dissipating the enchantments of antiquity, the nationalist world has amplified them into the vast cacophony of the late second millennium’ (p.17). 

Tom Nairn’s approach to the analytical study of nationalism is rooted. He wrote ‘I have never hidden the fact that my own dilemmas and oddities emanate from those of my country, Scotland. These undoubtedly explain a good deal of my intellectual passions and concerns. It is easier for others to sense, interpret and make fun of this, but I have not tried to evade it’ (p.180). Above all, he is intrigued by the accidental nature of nationalism in Scotland, that ‘the fate of a population which had conserved institutional nationality without statehood, and therefore never had to have a state for its own national identity to survive’ (ibid.) and as a result does not tie it into blood-and-soil ideology; that it is, in the truism, civic not ethnic. 

What emerged, in his view, was a ‘unique castrate form’ of nationalism, devoted to low politics but uncomfortable with high politics. Thus, it is replete with dualities: ‘firewater Hyde’ vis-à-vis ‘feartie Jekyll’, a process of ‘self-colonisation, a distinguished sort of soul malady’. Those familiar with Tom’s writings will recognise his explanation, notably in The Break-Up of Britain, for the cultural deformities associated with the ‘tartan monster’. Furthermore, ‘a famously educated culture produced no intelligentsia’ (204), which seems a bit harsh, or rather draws attention to the kind that Tom would be happy to endorse. He has no truck with notions of ‘civil society’ either, observing that ‘… if we have to speak about “civil societies” in the plural, might we not as well speak about nations, nationalities or countries, and so be more widely understood?’ (p88). He finds ‘civil society’ a ‘deeply mysterious term’ (p.203). He shouldn’t do, because there is no simple correspondence between ‘culture’ and ‘politics’. We require focus on the social carriers of these dimensions lest we stray into a sort of Hegelian idealism in which ideas have their own prior force. 

Those of us involved in Scotland’s intellectual conversations such as myself and Lindsay Paterson think there is considerable mileage in this notion to help account for Scotland having crossed the great divide before nationalism was the main political vehicle. In short, modernity in Scotland, and its social class cadres, did not require nationalism to bring it to power and influence, especially in the context of British empire. You do not have to buy into the Tom Nairn account of Scotland, and ‘the more celebrated Kitschland which stand in for Scotland in the world’s consciousness’ (p.207) to appreciate how stimulating his writings are, even – especially – when we disagreed with him. We are required by the sheer force of his argument to improve upon our own.

Tom also put his finger on one of the key aspects of nationalism in Scotland; that there is what he calls an orthographic battle between upper and lower case, Nationalism and nationalism, which remains at the core of Scottish politics. Or, as Tom observes, somewhere in between, ‘a position corresponding perhaps to “small caps” in font design’ (p. 196). 

The final essay in Faces of Nationalism is based on a talk Tom gave at Birkbeck College following the 1997 Blair election. The last sentence of this essay, and the book, observes, perceptively: ‘The 1997 election result opens the door to (at least) begin an escape from it [that is, the British state]. I hope we can get some way through that door before it closes again’ (p.224). Did we? Twenty-seven years later, and in a similar political context (I write at a moment when a Labour government has just been elected), we have a devolved parliament, we had a referendum on independence almost a decade ago, we were forced out of the European Union against our will. The keepers of the British state – Conservatives and Labour- have let it be known that a ScIndyRef2 is not on offer, underpinned by the black letter lawyers of the UK Supreme Court who say that it is none of our legal business. We have no obvious escape route from the British state, short of serious social and political upheaval, or a major revolution in the economic, social and constitutional apparatus of the UK, which looks the less likely of the two options. The UK state itself has locked itself into its tight little island on the fringe of Europe, with little inclination or likelihood to get back in, clutching Scotland to its bosom lest it is diminished in consequence. Tom would have enjoyed those ironies, and would have been tempted to say: There: I told you so.

Comments (15)

Join the Discussion

Your email address will not be published.

  1. SleepingDog says:

    I think we can do without old farts telling us what the true subject of modern philosophy is. Perhaps we should pay more attention to the philosophical questions raised by science fiction, for example.

    1. Graeme Purves says:

      Shouldn’t we be open to relevant and helpful ideas from whatever source they come? The success of the ‘Break-Up of Britain’ event in Edinburgh last November and the high intellectual quality of the contributions it elicited suggest that a lot of people find value and inspiration in Tom Nairn’s perpectives.

      1. SleepingDog says:

        @Graeme Purves, yes, I phrased my point unhelpfully, it was late at night. It was the repeated quotes in the article about the true (or *only* true) subject of modern philosophy that were the truly narrow (I could say, bigoted) viewpoints. I only came up with one general counter-example of interest, but had others in mind.

        The questioning of a child may be far more philosophically relevant to our future than any stack of dead academics. And yes, I count Greta Thunberg as a modern philosopher.

        My larger point, which I think agrees with yours, is that philosophy is essentially an open and universal questioning system, and therefore should be boundless, ranging over all subjects. Any attempt to steer it down one tiny subject route is anathema, and one wonders why anyone would try to limit it so. The reason I gave the example of science fiction is that so many scenarios transcend current nationalism (or industrialisation).

        Other views I’ve read on Tom Nairn’s work suggest a difficult or opaque style, and a lack of addressing obvious issues which seemed a fundamental flaw, so I haven’t bothered reading them. If they inspire others, fine. Perhaps his best ideas now circulate and I’m using some without knowing, also fine. But anyone who dictates (even in jest, assuming the quotation is correct) what the subject of modern philosophy should be, is as immediately suspect as anyone claiming that the proper study of man is man. More so. It’s what an academic might say, not a scholar, nor worthy of a philosopher.

        1. Graeme Purves says:

          I saw the rival claims about the ‘true subject of modern philosophy’ as essentially rhetorical and provocative and therefore not to be taken too literally.

          1. SleepingDog says:

            @Graeme Purves, sure, context is crucial. But these are anti-intellectual statements, and I wonder what purpose such rhetoric serves. It reminds me of the ‘outrageous’ statements of the postmodernists which contained reactionary agendas.

            Any recommendations on Tom Nairn’s best essay? My to-read pile is rather daunting already. And how would you summarise the Break-Up of Britain event?

          2. Gerry Hassan says:

            There are many Tom Nairn books which are worthy of reading and which are rich, rewarding and thought provoking.

            ‘The Break-Up of Britain’ first published in 1977 is his most penetrating work but some of it is a bit dense text wise.

            The book under review: ‘Faces of Nationalism’ first published in 1998 is a collection of previously published essays with a set of linking themes; and gives a grounding in Nairn on nationalism, Scotland, the UK and more.

          3. Alasdair Macdonald says:

            I have, over the years read most of Tom Nairn’s work.

            As Mr Hassan says, he “is a bit dense textwise”. Indeed, too often, I find his prose often very elliptical and consequently, the meaning is often occluded.

            On balance, I think his analysis, insofar as I can comprehend it, is insightful, but I think his style does not do justice to what I think he is saying.

          4. Everybody’s different I suppose Alasdair, I really love his writing style

  2. florian albert says:

    It looks like its ‘Let’s talk about Tom Nairn’ time again. Nairn is an individual whom the Scottish intelligentsia loves discussing but whom the general public remains largely unaware of.
    The main ideas he put forward were; the collapse of the UK an a unitary polity was a real possibility; there is a benign side to nationalism and the EEC/EU offered the prospect of prosperity to the working class.
    Without knowing of him or his ideas, ordinary people had largely already accepted these ideas. (If pushed they may have thought that his prognosis for the UK was unduly pessimistic.)

    There is a similarity here with recent events in the USA. Ordinary people could see that President Biden was semi-senile. Only among the intelligentsia was this a heretical idea.

    1. Gerry Hassan says:

      When you make that comment abt Tom Nairn, the Scottish intelligentsia and general public, that is true the world over of intellectuals and deep thinkers. So no change there.

      1. I think we’re maybe worse here – Scotland has a real problem in embracing thinkers and I think this is partly because we don’t recognise our own history of ideas

        1. SleepingDog says:

          @Editor, or maybe the problem is in trying to own our “own history of ideas”? Just a note to proselytisers: maybe if you want to get people to read an author, not rely on ‘bantz’?

      2. florian albert says:

        I made critical comments about one Scottish intellectual. From this you generalize – within five minutes of my making my comment – that this is ‘true the world over of intellectuals and deep thinkers.’
        As a defence of Tom Nairn as a thinker, this fails to convince.

  3. Niemand says:

    Very interesting read, thought provoking, thanks.

    A few things that just seem untrue / skewed in perspective though:

    Patriotism and nationalism are not the same thing. Orwell was right: the distinction is not inoperable but if it really doesn’t stand ‘analytical scrutiny’ then that scrutiny needs to be stated not simply asserted.

    Civic nationalism has certainly been at the helm of the movement for independence but the idea the ethnic sort is absent by default because Scotland has ‘never had to have a state for its own national identity to survive’ is a clever argument but one that flies in the face of reality. Ethnic nationalism, though in the minority, is alive and well in the independence movement and always has been, and in fact is growing.

    I never understood the negative analysis of ‘the black letter lawyers [?] of the UK Supreme Court’ saying ‘that it is none of our legal business’ since that challenge by the SNP looked like very costly theatre since the devolution agreement was very clear on what any outcome was going to be beforehand. Complaints about the court decision are empty, unless one assumes that Scotland somehow already has the rights of an independent nation, even though it is not, and arguments are based on this hypothetical assumption. The same approach applies to the Brexit vote though that one does clearly highlight one serious disadvantage of being in the UK when UK-wide votes are called.

    Finally one crucial aspect that is missed in the passage about there being ‘no obvious escape route from the British state’, and arguably the most important – increase support for independence to a sustained level notably well above 50% (it was 45% in 2014 and now, on average barely gets to 50 and hovers mostly around 47%, despite everything that has happened in between – Brexit, Johnson; Truss!!). Any arguments about rightful escape can only be built on a sustained clear majority support for independence.

  4. SleepingDog says:

    So, I have a problem with the assertion ending this article: “The UK state itself has locked itself into its tight little island on the fringe of Europe”.

    This is, in very important ways, false.

    I’d prefer it if summarisers would anticipate the questions of people unfamiliar with the body of works in question, otherwise I’d be better asking ChatGPT.

    Let’s see if you can guess my question, given the following hints. What territory had the strictest prohibitions on abortion in Europe up until 2021, and was referenced in a recent sporting tournament celebration stushie? What territory was a staging post both for events in Egypt 1882 and 1956, and Gaza today? Which international courts have ruled that the UK acted unlawfully in the last few years?

Help keep our journalism independent

We don’t take any advertising, we don’t hide behind a pay wall and we don’t keep harassing you for crowd-funding. We’re entirely dependent on our readers to support us.

Subscribe to regular bella in your inbox

Don’t miss a single article. Enter your email address on our subscribe page by clicking the button below. It is completely free and you can easily unsubscribe at any time.